World Library  
Flag as Inappropriate
Email this Article

Causal Theory of Knowledge

Article Id: WHEBN0033456414
Reproduction Date:

Title: Causal Theory of Knowledge  
Author: World Heritage Encyclopedia
Language: English
Subject: Epistemology, Reliabilism, Causality, Alvin Goldman, Structuralism (philosophy of mathematics)
Collection:
Publisher: World Heritage Encyclopedia
Publication
Date:
 

Causal Theory of Knowledge

A Causal Theory of Knowing is a philosophical essay written by Alvin Goldman in 1967, published in The Journal of Philosophy. It is based on existing theories of knowledge in the realm of epistemology, the study of philosophy through the scope of knowledge. The essay attempts to explain the sensation of knowledge by connecting facts, beliefs and knowledge through underlying and connective series called causal chains.

A causal chain is repeatedly described as a sequence of events for which one event in a chain causes the next. According to Goldman, these chains can only exist with the presence of an accepted fact, a belief of the fact, and a cause for the subject to believe the fact.[1] The essay also explores the ideas of perception and memory through the use the causal chains and the concept of knowledge.

Background

The essay is regarded as an improvement and rebuttal of Edmund Gettier's “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge,” which is one of many attempts to explain the necessary conditions for knowledge to develop. Gettier insists that knowledge is formed through a proposition for which someone has evidence that is true, and a belief that is justified through the fact.[2] However, Goldman implements the causal connection to reiterate his own theory of knowledge. Knowledge exists, says Goldman, if and only if the belief is justified by a reaction to the accepted fact.

Goldman’s theory later counters that of Michael Clark, stating that his own theory including figures and diagrams is more appropriate than Clark’s. A Causal Theory of Knowing uses figures which make explicit references to causal beliefs. Clark’s model does not utilize these arrows, and Goldman states that the lack of these arrows deems Clark’s model deficient.[3]

Author

Alvin Goldman, currently a professor of philosophy at Rutgers University, wrote A Causal Theory of Knowing when he was in his late twenties. Goldman received his Ph.D. from Princeton University, and has taught at numerous universities[4]

Goldman’s research deals mainly with epistemology and other cognitive sciences. A Causal Theory of Knowing was Goldman’s first published paper explaining his own views of epistemology. Currently, Goldman has written more than ten essays focusing on knowledge and cognitive science.

Contents

The essay starts with a definition of Gettier’s theory, followed by multiple reiterations of the idea of causal connections, figures to explain knowledge through a visual perspective, and references to perception and memory through causal chains.

The essay tends to focus on examples in which knowledge or other sensations do not exist, rather than proving a certain fact to be known. Goldman also states on multiple occasions that he does not wish to explain the causal process in detail, instead pointing out counter examples.[5] At numerous times in the essay, he also points out that he does not intend to give definitive answers to each of the propositions mentioned.[6]

Goldman also refocuses the idea of perception, or knowledge through sensation (specifically sight) using his own theory of knowing. The concept of causal perception indicates that one observes something only if the object itself causes the sensation of sight to be accepted as known. Thus, the object’s existence must be factual and one must believe its existence. While all knowledge comes from facts, inferred knowledge emerges when physical object facts cause sense data which can be perceived as senses. The sense data can also be used to make conclusions, known as inferred knowledge, about certain physical object facts.[7]

From A Causal Theory of Knowing, Goldman constructs the idea that memory is also a causal process. Memory is explained as being an extension of knowledge into the future, and remembering is the act of recalling a fact that has already been known. Further, the theory states that if knowledge is forgotten at one time, it cannot be considered a memory in the future. According to Goldman, if a fact is known at Time 1 but forgotten at Time 2, and then at Time 3 that the fact is perceived again but not known, at Time 3 the original fact is not a memory because there is no causal connection between the fact and the memory.

Reception

Much like Goldman’s essay contrasts those of philosophers before him, Kenneth Collier rebuts A Causal Theory of Knowing. In 1973, Collier’s short essay against the theory of causal knowledge was published. Collier found a hole in the theory of causal knowledge by supposing that a subject had been treated with a hallucinogenic drug. Collier claims that no causal theorist can explain the beliefs that occur as a result of this circumstance because while the subject may believe something that may also be a fact, the belief has no causal chain to the fact because of the drug.[8]

Footnotes

References

  • Kenneth W. Collier, “Contra the Causal Theory of Knowing,” Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition 24, no. 5 (Sep., 1973), pp. 350–352 http://www.jstor.org/stable/4318800
  • Alvin I. Goldman, “A Causal Theory of Knowing,” The Journal of Philosophy 64, no. 12 (Jun. 22, 1967), pp. 357–372 http://www.jstor.org/stable/2024268
  • Edmund L. Gettier, “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?” Analysis 23, No. 6 (Jun., 1963), pp. 121–123 http://www.jstor.org/stable/3326922
  • Alvin I. Goldman, “Professional Biography,” (Aug. 21, 2007) http://fas-philosophy.rutgers.edu/goldman/Professional%20Biography.pdf

External links

This article was sourced from Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License; additional terms may apply. World Heritage Encyclopedia content is assembled from numerous content providers, Open Access Publishing, and in compliance with The Fair Access to Science and Technology Research Act (FASTR), Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., Public Library of Science, The Encyclopedia of Life, Open Book Publishers (OBP), PubMed, U.S. National Library of Medicine, National Center for Biotechnology Information, U.S. National Library of Medicine, National Institutes of Health (NIH), U.S. Department of Health & Human Services, and USA.gov, which sources content from all federal, state, local, tribal, and territorial government publication portals (.gov, .mil, .edu). Funding for USA.gov and content contributors is made possible from the U.S. Congress, E-Government Act of 2002.
 
Crowd sourced content that is contributed to World Heritage Encyclopedia is peer reviewed and edited by our editorial staff to ensure quality scholarly research articles.
 
By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. World Heritage Encyclopedia™ is a registered trademark of the World Public Library Association, a non-profit organization.
 



Copyright © World Library Foundation. All rights reserved. eBooks from World eBook Library are sponsored by the World Library Foundation,
a 501c(4) Member's Support Non-Profit Organization, and is NOT affiliated with any governmental agency or department.